Irrational Happiness

When I started writing this blogpost a week ago, I wrote this: “When times are as difficult and unpredictable as they are today, I find comfort in mathematics. No matter how things turn out, how many more difficulties come our way, we may be certain that mathematics stays the way it is* – it is our indestructable beacon of rationality. In this blogpost I want to share with you some of the comfort that mathematics gives to me.”

But the longer I think about these things, the more I realise that it is not this comfort that I want to share. I realise that when I am at home alone, sitting in my ‘internest’, writing this blog, I forget about all the trouble around me. I stop worrying about the coronavirus or about my recent divorce. Mathematics makes me happy, that’s what I want to share!


Pythagoras (c. 570 – c. 495 BC)

Just like me, the followers of Pythagoras in the sixth century BC really loved their numbers. When one of them discovered that there are numbers, like √2, which you can’t write out in all their decimals, because they have infinitely many of them (√2=1.41421356237…), the other Pythagoreans threw the poor fellow into the sea. But his death hasn’t helped. Numbers with infinitely many decimals exist, and √2 is one of them.

To prove that √2 has infinitely many decimals, we must show that it can’t be written as the division of two whole numbers – that √2 is an irrational number (so-called because it is not the ratio between two whole numbers).

If mathematical proof isn’t your favourite pass-time (not even in quarantine) then perhaps you should skip to the paragraph ‘Hamlet’s nutshell’.

Talk contradictory to me baby!

The proof that √2 is an irrational number is a proof by contradiction. We assume that the opposite of what we want to prove, the statement “√2 is the ratio between two whole numbers”, is true, and from that we derive a contradiction, so that we know that the assumption that we started with is false.

So we start with the assumption that √2 is the ratio between two whole numbers. Let’s begin by writing the ratio in terms of its smallest divisors, the lowest values of m and n for which the ratio stays the same (so that 3/6 becomes 1/2, 5/15 becomes 1/3 and 2/1200 becomes 1/600). Let’s call these smallest divisors m and n. To derive the contradiction that we need for our proof, we will show that the m and the n that go into √2 are even numbers, which means that \frac{m}{n} is not the ratio between two smallest divisors (because both terms in the ratio can be divided by two). But the assumption that we started with is that m and n are the smallest divisors, so if our reasoning is correct, our starting assumption must be wrong.

Let’s begin with this:

\sqrt{2}=\frac{m}{n}

square both sides to get

2 = \left( \frac{m}{n} \right)\textsuperscript{2} = \frac{m^2}{n^2}

then multiply both sides by n^2 to get

2n^2=m^2

If m and n are arbitrary whole numbers, then so are m^2 and n^2. So if n^2 is equal to some arbitrary whole number multiplied by two, m^2 must be an even number (because any number multiplied by 2 is an even number). Ok, so we know that m^2 is even, but what about m? Is m also even, if m^2 is even? m appears in our equation in its squared form, but whatever the value of m^2, there are only two possibilities: m is either even or odd (mathematicians like stating the obvious). But how does that help us? How can we explore these two possibilities?

We’re going to use a little trick here: we know that a number is an even number if it can be divided by 2, so if m is an even number, we may write m=2k, where k is again some arbitrary number. Think about it. If some arbitrary number is one of these “1, 2, 3, 4, 5…” then two times that number is in the list “2, 4, 6, 8…”. This gives us a list of even numbers, but how do we get to the odd numbers? The second part of our trick is to add 1 to every number in the list of even numbers, so that we get a list with odd numbers (“3, 5, 7, 9…”), so we know that we can write any odd number as 2k+1. Try it yourself, fill in “1, 2, 3, 4, 5…” for k in 2k+1 and you get “3, 5, 7, 9…”.

Back to our two possibilities. We know that m^2 is even, but what about m? Is m even or odd? Where do these possibilities lead us?

Possibilities

If 1: m is even, we know that m=2k for an arbitrary k, so that m^2= \left( 2k \right)^2=4k^2, which is again an even number because it is divisible by two. We now know that \sqrt{2}=\frac{m}{n} is consistent with m^2 and m being both even.

If 2: m is odd, then we may write m=2k+1 for some arbitrary number k, so that m^2= \left( 2k + 1 \right) \left( 2k+1 \right) = 4k^2 + 4k+1. This expression has the form “even number + 1”, because 4k^2 + 4k is even, so 4k^2 + 4k+1 must be odd. We see that the second possibility leads to saying “if m is odd, then m^2 is also odd.”

Before we started talking about the two possibilities, we asked “what can we say about m if we know that m^2 is even?” We see that assuming that m is odd leads to an m^2 which is odd, so possibility 2 is not a possibility at all! The only remaining option is possibility 1: if m^2 is even, then m is also even.

Are we there yet? We started this blogpost by saying that it is impossible that \sqrt{2}=\frac{m}{n} if m and n are smallest divisors because \sqrt{2}=\frac{m}{n} implies that m and n are even, but we haven’t shown that yet. We know that from m^2 = 2n^2 it follows that both m and m^2 are even, but what about n? Let’s use our ‘little trick’ again. Since we know that m is an even number, we may write m = 2k. We also know that m^2=2n^2, which gives us 4k^2=2n^2. Divide both sides by 2, and we see that 2k^2=n^2, which tells us that n^2 is an even number. We know from our earlier reasoning that if the square of an arbitrary number is even, then so is the number itself (if m^2 is even then m is even). We just showed that n^2 is even, so n itself must also be even.

Phiew! We have finally reached the contradiction. Both m and n are even, so they are not the smallest divisors in \sqrt{2}=\frac{m}{n}. This contradicts our starting assumption, so that assumption must be false, so √2 is not a rational number.

Q.E.D.**

Something keeps nagging, though. We have shown that both m and n are even, which tells us that m and n are not the smallest divisors in \sqrt{2}=\frac{m}{n}, but what does that tell us? We assumed that they were smallest divisors, and that’s why there was a contradiction. What if we don’t make this assumption? What if we assume that there are numbers m and n such that \sqrt{2}=\frac{m}{n}, for some m and n that are not the smallest divisors in \frac{m}{n}?

What we should realise is that both m and n could be any number, so if we say \sqrt{2}=\frac{m}{n}, then this equation must hold for all choices of m and n, including the choice where m and n are smallest divisors. m and n being the smallest divisors is not an extra assumption – it is part of the assumption that m and n are arbitrary numbers.

Can’t we make a claim about √2 that is a bit weaker? What if we say that m and n are numbers for which \sqrt{2}=\frac{m}{n} does not have smallest divisors? Will that allow us to say that √2 is a ratio between whole numbers?

Nice try, but it won’t work. Or rather, it works, but then the m and n that go into √2 are not numbers as we know them. Take any pair of positive, whole numbers, and make a rational number out of them \left(\frac{m}{n}\right). Depending on the choice you make, it is either possible to divide both n and m by some other number (so that, for example, \frac{3}{6} becomes \frac{1}{2}, and \frac{4}{16} becomes \frac{1}{4}) or you can’t do that, in which case you have the smallest divisors (\frac{1}{2}, \frac{5}{8}, \frac{6}{7}). The possibility left for m and n that neither have nor are smallest divisors of √2, is to choose for m and n some trans-finite numbers, such as \aleph_0, which represents, among other things, the cardinality of the set of all integers. But the moment we start talking about trans-finite numbers, we leave the realm of the real and the rational numbers. The ratio which trans-finite numbers can give us is not a rational number.

Hamlet’s nutshell

It makes me a bit dizzy when I start thinking about trans-finite numbers (if you’ve skipped the proof, just believe me when I say that trans-finite numbers are stranger than fiction). Math-induced dizziness is a pleasant dizziness, much as that due to a glass of whisky. It reminds me of something that Shakespeare’s Hamlet says:

“I could be bounded in a nutshell, and count myself a king of infinite space”

No matter what happens, no matter what comes our way or how isolated I become, in my mind I can instantly travel to the farthest reaches of human understanding. Simply by following the rules of logic.


*) which is not to say that it’s impossible that mathematicians discover new theorems or new mathematical relations. What I mean is that mathematics, as logical reasoning about numbers, will continue, no matter what.

**) Nerd-speak for ‘I told you so’. Also sometimes “quod erat demonstrandum” (Latin for ‘…which needed to be proved’)

About fbenedictus

Philosopher of physics at Amsterdam University College and Utrecht University, managing editor for Foundations of Physics and international paraclimbing athlete
This entry was posted in AUC-Big Questions in Science, Philosophy of Mathematics, Philosophy of Physics and tagged , , , , , , , , , . Bookmark the permalink.

4 Responses to Irrational Happiness

  1. Chris says:

    Fedde, you are a great man. The world needs people like you as examples. Continue on your way. AUB, ga verder vooruit.

  2. Bob Cole says:

    Hi Fedde,

    Interesting until it became incomprehensible …to me that is. I like the image of the others looking over Pythagoras’ shoulder and copying his maths.
    To the point! I wonder if you could spare maybe 10 minutes of your valuable time to give us an opinion of an article we have been sent for publication. ‘We’ are the Lewis Carroll Society based in London and have a scholarly biannual publication called the Carrollian, your friend Bas is familiar with it as he is a member. The article is either a work of tremendous erudition and intellect or nonsense. But which? We are not physicists but we have an opinion.
    It is 2 1/2 pages long. Would you be good enough to look at it??

    I can’t find a working email address for you so send this, perhaps inappropriately, to your comments address. Hope that is OK.

    Cheers Bob Cole.

  3. Marco van Hulten says:

    It’s good to see that it is mathematics that makes you going amid all the shit! As a bonus—on top of the fun—, «mathematics saves lives both in medicine and through climate research.» [1].

    [1]: http://www.realclimate.org/index.php/archives/2020/03/coronavirus-and-climate/

Leave a Reply